Book Review: The Ego Tunnel: The Science of the Mind and the Myth of
the Self
by Thomas Metzinger (Basic
Books 2009)
This ‘cutting edge’ book melds philosophy of consciousness
with cognitive neuroscience. Metzinger is a philosopher. Though written for the
lay reader, it is hard to follow at times. Quite a lot of concepts,
relationships, and terminology are introduced. However, he does re-explain
things enough so that the theory makes sense if one persists. He endeavors to
cover the issues current in consciousness research and even offers interviews
with various researchers and neuroscientists. Some of the subjects are
emotions, dreaming and so-called astral phenomena, empathy, free will, AI, and
the ethics of cultivating various states of consciousness. The starting point
and the overriding theory throughout the book is that the realization that
there is no entity that is us, as we normally perceive us – that our reality is
a virtual reality based on a model of the self that evolved along with our
human form of consciousness.
One of the key concepts, or metaphors, of the book is the
Phenomenal Self-Model (PSM). He describes it with the help of a now famous
experiment first done at the University
of Pittsburgh , called the
‘rubber-hand illusion’. In the experiment the person sticks their hands through
holes in a window in such a way that one hand is concealed and one sees an
artificial hand in place of it. Repeatedly, including with the author, the
experiment shows that when one thinks one is seeing the hand, though actually
the virtual hand, one feels it as the hand and reacts as if it were the hand.
What one actually feels is what he calls the ‘content’ of the phenomenal
self-model. The word “phenomenal” refers to phenomenology which is concerned
with the reporting of how things appear to one. For example, color only exists
as it is created by our sensory apparatus – other organisms see something
different. One might also use the analogy of the “Plato’s Cave”
metaphor/parable – where one believes in a reality based only on what one has
experienced. When one experiences beyond this, so too does the reality expand.
“The PSM of Homo
sapiens is probably one of nature’s best inventions. It is an efficient way
to allow a biological organism to consciously conceive of itself (and others)
as a whole. Thus it enables the organism to interact with its internal world as
well as with the external environment in an intelligent and holistic manner.”
He notes that animals, though having consciousness, have a
different PSM than humans. Along with the rubber-hand illusion there are other
phenomena that suggest the PSM: out-of body experiences (OBE) and artificial
limb syndrome are among them. The body double, body image, or astral body of
OBE is also the ‘content’ of the PSM. The ‘ego’ dwells in this body model. We
perceive the parts of our body as belonging to us which strengthens this
ego-illusion. Thus the ego, as it appears, exists in a ‘tunnel’. Our sense of
self, says Metzinger, is “a form of conscious representational content.” The
reason it is called a tunnel is that we only perceive a fraction of what is
really there as our senses evolved merely to ensure our survival rather than to
experience all that is possible to experience.
“Modern neuroscience has demonstrated that the content of
our conscious experience is not only an internal construct but also an
extremely selective way of representing information.”
Thus the concept of the “Ego Tunnel” is the central metaphor
of the book. The PSM is the model. The ego, or “I” or self, is what is in the
model. He also calls it a “self-model theory of subjectivity”. A key feature of
the model is that it is transparent,
so that we do not normally recognize it. It is a brain simulation. It is not
reality but an image of reality. This configuration (ego in tunnel) is “evolved
representational phenomena, a result of dynamical self-organization on many
levels.” The idea of the ego tunnel is based on earlier ideas of the “reality
tunnel” found in virtual reality research and promulgated by those he calls
non-academic philosophers – namely Robert Anton Wilson and Timothy Leary. The
basic idea is that we do not see reality as it is because we filter it
(automatically and unconsciously) and so construct our own version, or model of
reality.
He also talks about the search for a “neural correlate of
consciousness” (NCC) and specifically a global neural correlate of
consciousness. The NCC is defined as a “set of neurofunctional properties in
your brain sufficient to bring about a conscious experience.” Correlation does
not mean causation so discovering these correlates (ie. what happens in the
brain during events) does not really explain consciousness. But such discovery
can help with the future neuro-technology of inducing states of consciousness.
Consciousness is defined as “the appearance of a world.”
Human consciousness developed special features so that we can model our models,
be conscious of our consciousness, etc. These are “higher-order” levels of the
PSM, he says. In considering the possible effects of knowledge of knowledge
(ie. epistemology) he notes the extremes of ‘reductionism’ – reducing
everything to one simplistic theory, and ‘mysterianism’ – favoring the
impossibility of knowing much about consciousness. He does admit that there are
other ways of knowing besides science.
Metzinger describes six problems that need to be solved in
formulating a philosophical and neurological theory of consciousness. The first
he calls the one-world problem: the
unity of consciousness. The ‘one world problem; is described like this: “In
order for a world to appear to us, it has to be one world first.” He gives examples of psychiatric disorders –
sometimes due to brain lesions – where people can’t recognize what they are
seeing, touching, cannot name their limbs, or cannot integrate seeing and
hearing. Many of these disorders are versions of agnosia. Some neurologists speak of a “world-binding function” as
in the dynamical core hypothesis. The
neural properties underlying consciousness – the global NCC - may give us the
sense of the “unity of consciousness.” This sense of the unity or coherence of
consciousness may be virtual. It may be a result of the “global synchrony” of
neurons making it seem as if what is in the cloud of consciousness (the dynamical
core) is our subjective experience and what is not within the cloud is not part
of our subjective experience. Here is an interesting quote but the context is a
bit unclear. Regarding neurological experiments with “mathematical instruments”
he notes that “they show us how self-organization in our brains strikes an
optimal balance between integration and segregation, …” Consciousness may
create the world in the manner of “context loops” where the immediate past
conditions the present by creating a context for it. In visual perception, for
instance, this may occur in the time frame of micro-seconds. The synchrony of
neural responses may allow for the optimal balance between integration and
segregation as mentioned above. Neuronal firings are often in synch and/or in
rhythm which allows for information coding. Neuroscientists studying meditators
have noted clear “global phase-synchrony” on EEG readings of those who are very
experienced meditators. It is apparent that meditation can change the deep structure
of consciousness. With synchrony, intensity of firing, rate of firing, etc –
being the main information coding mechanisms, it can be seen that the unity of
consciousness is involved with ‘time’.
The next problem is called – the now problem – subjective experience of time is a necessary part
of consciousness. A major function of consciousness according to psychologist
Richard Gregory is “flagging the dangerous present,” Our inner model of time is
likely an adaptive mechanism. Our sense of presence is knowledge that can help
us survive. We experience simultaneity, succession, and duration as aspects of
time – our temporal gestalt. “Presence is a necessary condition for conscious
experience.” We have a sense of presence but we are not really in touch with
the presence because neural information processing takes time. Now is merely an
appearance we experience as now. The ego is inseparable from here and now. Our
sense of presence is our inner representation
of time.
Next is – the reality
problem. If the first two problems are solved we have a unified world and a
model of the present moment. Our world-models and now-models are transparent,
which is why we don’t experience them as representative models. The author
talks about higher-order representations.
For instance, a first-order process would be visual perception and a
second-order process would be attentional processing of visual perception.
While transparency may be caused by the speed of information-processing the
author suggests that it has more to do with the speed of processing of
different order processes relative to each other, ie. speed of visual
perception relative to speed of attentional processing of visual perception.
The bottom line is that the brain is invisible to itself. He suggests that the
reason the model stayed transparent to us is that it would not have been
cost-efficient in terms of metabolic
price (a concept whereby new ways of knowing/doing cost energy in terms of
sugar metabolism) to know that we were knowing, or to make images about images,
also known as metarepresentation. He
notes that “whatever appears to us – however it is mediated – appears as
reality.” The phenomenal transparency is
our “invisible interface to reality.” Situations where the transparency, the
transparent walls of the ego tunnel, disappear (in varying degrees), may
include dreams, lucid dreams, OBEs, NDEs, optical illusions, visions, hypnagogic
hallucinations, psychiatric maladies, and psychedelic drug experiences.
Next is – the
ineffability problem – much of the details of consciousness can’t be
recalled or communicated. The contents of consciousness can be ineffable in
several ways – we may not have language to describe certain things; describing
visual things to a blind person is not really effective; our ability to
discriminate things like subtle differences in color hues exceeds our ability
to form concepts about them. We can detect contrast in our sensory experiences
but we generally cannot identify or recognize the same exact event without it
being contrasted against the next value. We have limited perceptual memory.
There are those that have finer degrees of discrimination to detect nuances –
vintners, musicians, perfume designers. Conscious experience is so subtle that
the nuances can hardly be communicated. One must experience them for oneself.
The author suggests that one day neurobiological concepts may replace
inadequate phenomenological concepts but it is yet unclear how this would
occur.
Next is – the
evolution problem – why and exactly how the human form of consciousness
evolved is not known. Surely, it is built on previously evolved forms of animal
consciousness, both sensory and emotional. There are many possible avenues that
could have been taken to arrive at human consciousness. Many consciousness
researchers agree that one of the main functions of consciousness is making
information “globally available” to an organism. Attention may see with more
detail than memory or conceptual thought – and so has a higher degree of
availability. The author sees consciousness as a new kind of organ, a virtual organ. Other virtual
organs may include feelings, episodic memory, and immune response. Global
availability of information allows us to do many things:
“If you have a conscious, transparent world-model, you can,
for the first time, directly compare what is actual with what is only possible,
the actual world with simulated possible worlds you’ve designed in your mind.”
This functional property of comparing the actual to the
possible, he says, is an evolutionary step upon which everything else rests.
Offline simulations can plan online actions so this property allowed us to use
episodic memory to plan actions. We became able to utilize the past and
simulate the future in order to deal with the “dangerous present.” The
transparency of the model, he says, allowed us to see the difference between
the “real” world (though technically still a virtual world) and the many
possible worlds of simulation.
Finally, there is – the
who problem – “consciousness is always bound to an individual first-person
perspective.” Subjectivity is vague. Just who is “I”? A severe psychiatric
disorder called Cotard’s Syndrome is sometimes characterized by the person
claiming that they don’t exist. Some famed mystics have also come to this
conclusion based on their experiences of the loss of a sense of self. The sense
of unity in mystical experience perhaps points to the illusion of the limited
self within the tunnel. Metzinger speculates that the evolution of our immune
systems first developed determinations on the cellular level as to what is us
and what is not us, ie. the invader. That was perhaps the beginning of the
conceptual self/world distinction. Our self-model was likely based on our
world-model. Even so, the whole idea of the self and subjectivity is still
difficult to comprehend.
An interview with German neurophysiologist Wolf Singer
concludes the chapter where he talks about the “powerful self-organizing
mechanisms of the brain.” Many of these mechanisms are controlled by
“synchronized oscillatory discharges.” Precise synchronization of neuronal
events may account for (the apparent?) unity of consciousness. Singer notes
that a current big challenge is refining our knowledge of how information is
encoded in the brain: rate of firing, amplitudes and duration of discharges,
etc. Pattern searching through complex mathematical algorithms is a current
method of searching for precise encoding mechanisms in order to search for the
NCCs. He also suggests that future collaborations between cognitive
neuroscientists and philosophers and others in the humanities will be required
as more becomes known.
The body-mind nexus is next examined. Having a body gives us
a sense of ownership of it. The interplay between vision, touch, and proprioception
can be manipulated, as in the rubber-hand illusion, to alter the self-model. We
can utilize our body-image self-model to better use tools, thus integrating
vision, touch, and proprioception. The tool becomes part of the bodily self. It
seems likely that the evolution of tool use may have co-evolved to some extent
with the bodily self-model. Experiments have shown that monkeys, also tool
users, also have this sort of bodily self-model.
“… the evolution of language, culture, and abstract thought might
have been a process of “exaptation,” of using our body maps for new challenges
and purposes.”
OBEs are the next subject. He talks about it as a taboo
subject in philosophical circles when he was in school as materialism was in
vogue and any talk about soul components was stifled. He suggests that the
“soul” as a metaphysical concept may have arisen to from the phenomenological
concept of the experienced OBE. He says that the soul is the OBE-PSM. He goes
through several accounts of OBEs, several his own, and Susan Blackmore’s
interesting theory about them – that they are a conscious simulation of the
world from a third-person perspective that include a realistic body
representation that we think is real. We notice the body, not as subject, but
as object. The phenomena of “autoscopy,” of viewing one’s body from a distance,
is very related. There are autoscopic
hallucinatory experiences of four main types: autoscopy, heautoscopy –
changing bodies, OBE, and “feeling of a presence.” The phenomenology of OBEs
varies, with different methods of separating from the body and speeds of doing
so. Some sense themselves in another body while others feel they are bodiless.
OBEs were inadvertently induced in an epileptic patient in 2002 by Olaf Blanke
and colleagues, while using invasive neuro-imaging to try and find legions.
Electrical stimulation of the brain (ESB) has also been found to induce the
“feeling of a presence.” Blanke and colleagues note that two pathological
conditions are necessary to form an OBE: 1) “disintegration on the level of the
self-model brought about by a failure to bind proprioceptive, tactile, and
visual information about one’s body”, and 2) “conflict between external, visual
space and the internal frame of reference created by our vestibular organs.” We
see the body in a different position than we feel it. The author describes some
experiments done with Olaf and a colleague where he – the author – was the
subject – utilizing virtual reality hardware to try and create a whole body
version of the rubber-hand illusion. The results were not stellar but there was
identification with a mannequin by many of the subjects in the manner of the
rubber-hand illusion. The bodily self occupies space while the seeing self does
not. They can be effectively separated, says the author. The seeing self can be
turned off by closing the eyes, so is not the essence of selfhood. The author
suggests that we don’t know, but the closest we can get to an essence of
selfhood is: “location in space and time plus a transparent body image.” Attentional
agency, or self-directed attention allows for global availability, and thus a
sense of selfhood.
Conscious experience as the self-model is an interface, a
control device, a virtual world that allows us better control of the outside
world. The ego is a functional illusion. The human brain can be compared to a
modern flight simulator – continually constructing and updating an internal
model of external reality by filtering through the senses and past experience.
The difference is that our brain as a simulator is updated at such fast rates
and degrees of accuracy that we don’t recognize it as a model. The pilot of our
simulator is the non-existent ego.
Experiments with “phantom limb” victims (amputees who can
still sense their amputated limbs) have succeeded in getting them to feel a
sense of movement in those limbs, but only when their eyes were open to the
illusion given them. Since, coordinated bodily movements were needed for
survival, the bodily self-model developed to increase speed and coordination –
first among animals and then perhaps conceptually among humans.
There is another odd phenomenon, known as “Alien Hand
syndrome” where one loses control of a limb. The hand seems to have a “will” of
its own. The feeling of control, of self-willing actions, and of actions willed
by another – varies in different psychiatric maladies. The author asks on an
ultimate philosophical level- Are there willed actions or just events that
occur? Our sense of ownership (of our body) supports our sense of self which
then supports our sense of agency, ie. will. The author notes that: “the Ego is
a neurocomputational device for appropriating and controlling the body – first
the physical one and then the virtual one.” Attentional agency, or directing
(willing) the attention is a result of the consolidation of the ego tunnel.
Infants cannot do it – as their ego tunnel is not yet consolidated. In dreams
there is often consciousness without attentional control. Drunkenness and
senility may be other examples. Cognitive agency is selecting the contents of
your mind – experiencing yourself as a thinker of thoughts – a la Descartes
(pun intended). Moving the body, focusing attention, and selecting thoughts all
involve effort, so agency is associated with effort.
Agency can be hallucinated as ESB experiments confirm. We
can think we willed or intended an action when we didn’t. 1990’s trickery experiments
by psychologists Wegman and Wheatley caused people to think they were willing
actions when not and they concluded that the phenomenal experience of will
consists of three principles:
“The principle of exclusivity
holds that the subject’s thought should be the only introspectively available
cause of action; the principle of consistency
hold that the subjective intention should be consistent with the action; and
the principle of priority holds that
the thought should precede the action “in a timely manner””.
The sense of agency, the conscious experience of will,
allows us to see ourselves as pursuing goals and leads to optimizing means to
ends. It also allows us to know that others also have will of their own.
In examining the dream state he notes an example where a
person has a dream that they had an OBE and woke up and told someone about it –
but it was a false awakening. This
confounds the appearance/reality distinction. He suggests that it demonstrates
that consciousness is never more than the appearance of a world. The dream
tunnel also creates the appearance of a world but one without sensory-motor
activity. Dreams are unstable and tend to lack focused attention. The sense of
will is reduced. Emotions, however, can be enhanced in dreams. In lucid dreams
we may become aware of the ego tunnel. We know that we are in a simulated
world. Memory, a sense of agency, and sensory experience may remain intact in a
lucid dream. In fact, the sense of will can be strong – as when I was lucid
dreaming I was experimenting with the dream state willing different things –
which is also a technique of Indo-Tibetan dream yoga practices. Dr. Stephen LaBerge
of Stanford University was able to devise a means
where lucid dreamers could signal with their eye movements that they were
having a lucid dream. The author calls these rare examples of trans-tunnel
communications. Psychiatrist Alan Hobson has worked with discovering a neural
correlate of lucid dreaming. There is an interview with Hobson. He thinks that
dreaming is “our subjective awareness of our dream activation in any state of
sleep.” Activation is highest in REM sleep so that state is most associated
with dreaming. Stroke and frontal lobotomy victims often report a cessation of
dreaming depending on which parts of the brain were affected so dreaming, or
dream recall, is dependent on coordination of brain parts. Asked about the
evolutionary function of dreaming, Hobson first suggests that there may not be
one. If dream recall was adaptive we would have more of it. Other possibilities
of the function of dreams he suggests are “enhancement of motor learning, the
regulation of dietary and thermal calories, and the improvement of immune
functions.” Since mammals are homeothermic, brain activation during sleep helps
to regulate brain temperature in species that face variances in temperature and
environment. Hobson also notes that Freud’s psychoanalytic dream analysis and
wish fulfillment functions have mostly been refuted by neuroscience.
The Ego Tunnel has not only an inward perspective but also a
social aspect. The theory is that new layers to the self-model allowed the
transition from biological to cultural evolution. The transition in the
self-model from first-person singular (me) to first-person plural (we) allowed
for the beginning of moral agency. The new discipline of “social neuroscience” deals
with the social aspects of neurology. Neurologists first discovered a set of
neurons that respond to visual perception of objects in our environment. These canonical neurons are related to the use
of an inner motor vocabulary that deals with possible actions related to an
object. These neurons, he says, are precursors to the self-model. Another
related group of neurons, called mirror
neurons, are activated when we observe behavior in others and match or
emulate it. We map the actions of others onto our own model. We also note that
others also have goals. Mirror neuron systems can also be activated for
emotional states. This also gives a sort of neural correlate for empathy. We
can simulate the physical and emotional states of others using our own
self-model. The author thinks that the body-model was an adaptation and that
social cognition, stemming from the precursor actions of mirror neurons, was an
“exaptation”, a new use for the previously developed adaptation. Canonical
neurons could be the link between motor activity and primitive inner conceptual
language. Mirror neurons could be the precursor to communicating meaning to
others. He speculates that the precursor to language was gestural communication
rather than animal calls. Gestures communicate meaning better than calls. We
understand gestures because we do them too, having learned them from mirroring
or mimicking others. Interestingly, he notes, the word for grasping (at least
in Latin) is related to the word for concepts – and even now we say that we
“grasp a concept.” This is a possible relationship between motor-activity and
understanding meaning that may hark back to the formulation or adding of a new
layer to our self-model. There are clear neural relationships between movement
of the hand/arm and the mouth. It seems sensible to conclude that body language
is the foundation of verbal language. Mirror neurons may explain other
phenomena as well – the infectiousness of yawning and of laughter, the group
behaviors of schools of fish, flocks, of birds, herds, and even human social
conformity. These can be seen as forms of synchronization with one another.
There is an interview with Vittorio Gallese, a
neurophysiologist and an authority on mirror neurons. He expounds on his shared manifold hypothesis – which is our
link with others in understanding them through observation. He calls this
shared manifold an expanded idea of empathy. On the phenomenological level
there is a sense of similarity and familiarity when we encounter others – that
we are part of a shared social sphere. Functionally, there is “embodied
simulation” of actions, emotions, and sensations observed in others.
Subpersonally, there is the action of the mirroring neural circuits. Generally,
when we are with others, we become “we-centric”, at least to some extent.
Mirror neuron activity suggests that we empathize unconsciously and
automatically by modeling others’ behavior. Such systems may have evolved
through the need to accurately read the intentions of others to increase
survivability. He mentions “orders of intentionality”, ie. “I know that you
know that I know, etc.” We learn best by imitation which may well involve
mirror neurons. Even repeatedly hearing the narration of a story may involve
mirror neurons so they are activated in language processing. Imitation, and the
empathizing the underlies it, is very important to cultures with strong oral
traditions. Mirroring neural circuitry is likely being effected by new forms of
media as well, from books to cinema to internet, says Gallese. He also notes
that cognitive neuroscience and philosophy of mind deal with the same problems
but utilize different approaches and so should be utilized in tandem.
Next, there is a discussion of Artificial Ego Machines,
which refers to AI systems that simulate ego tunnels in some way. This part of
the book I found to be speculative and not all that interesting, maybe because
it is in its infancy. There are a lot of “what ifs” here. He examines the
ethical implications of developing artificial ego machines as well – noting
that we would be better off working on reducing human suffering first.
The final section on Consciousness Technologies is
interesting. Ultimately, the Ego and its Tunnel is a model of a model of
reality. There can be many ways to model reality. We can see the self as
process – we can say we are “selfing”. He does seem adamant in concluding that
there is no “ghost in the machine, no Ego in the Tunnel, no definable entity we
can call self. There is only “dynamical self-organization.” He suggests that we
cannot really understand consciousness without radically transforming our state
of consciousness. He notes that:
“Obviously, the evolutionary process that created our
bodies, our brains, and our conscious minds was not a goal-directed chain of
events.”
He sees our evolutionary development as the result of
“bottom-up self-organization.”
He does note that knowledge of the tunnel by groups of
scientists is actually invading the tunnel. Consciousness of our consciousness
is affecting our consciousness. The fact of mortality is an existential
conflict. We are selfless ego machines longing for immortality. Are we the
evolutionary products of goal-less chance?
The author suggests that a “philosophically motivate
neuroanthropology” may gain in importance as neurological advances weaken
traditional religious views. What is a human and what should a human become may
be the key questions of this science. Will weakening of religion weaken ethics?
I doubt it, as ideas like ethics and compassion seem intuitively important,
regardless of religious dogma. The author talks of a “recursive” process that
may alter the contents, structure, and function of our self-model:
“The world evolved world-modelers. Parts began to mirror the
whole.”
“More important, the world evolved self-modelers who were
able to form groups…… Through science, the dynamic processes of self-modeling
and world-modeling were extended into the symbolic, the social, and the
historical dimensions: We became rational theory-makers.”
The author considers the idea of consensual agreement on
what constitutes desirable states of consciousness. Shamans, yogis, mystics,
drug users, and others have explored consciousness through the means available:
herbs, drugs, fasting, drumming, dancing, fear, pain, ecstasy, etc. Now we have
at least crude neurological explanations for many of these states. With newer
drugs and brain manipulation techniques (neurotechnology) we have opportunities
for “cognitive enhancement.” I remember the beginnings of the “smart drug”, or
“nootropics” scene in the 80’s but not much seems to have been done since then
from my perspective – but maybe I’m wrong, maybe I just have not kept up.
Persinger’s “temporal-lobe” theory of religious/mystical experience and
personality shifts was an early attempt at finding neural correlates to these
experiences. In a study from the journal Nature
it was revealed that scientists that use cognitive enhancers, preferred
methylphenidate (Ritalin). in order to stimulate focus, concentration, and
memory. Others preferred modafinil. The author examines the ethical
implications of cognitive enhancers and the possibilities that there may be
tens of thousands of variant drugs on the markets, white and black, in the
years to come. Drug policy will have to determine which brain-states will be
illegal and which legal.
The internet is merging with our self-model. On-line
addiction can be problematic but the trade-offs are acceptable. The internet,
for all it is, is also a consciousness technology. Attention management is an
issue we face. Attention is finite. We can only “attend” to so many things at
once or in the space of a day. The author proposes childhood development in
attention management through such forms as training in meditation. Development
of a rational and ethical “consciousness culture” is another avenue he
explores.
Great book. Difficult at times. Lots of terminology and
abstract ideas.
No comments:
Post a Comment